
Since its debut in 1999, The Matrix franchise, directed by The Wachowskis, has intrigued, mystified, and even perplexed audiences. The films’ intricate plots, dense philosophical underpinnings, and groundbreaking visual effects have led some viewers to perceive them as complex and difficult to follow. However, for those willing to look beneath the surface spectacle, The Matrix offers a profound meditation on one of the most essential questions of human existence: the nature of freedom and choice.









For me, The Matrix was never confusing—it was exhilarating. Beneath the layers of CGI and action sequences, I saw a deeply compelling story about free will, autonomy, and the philosophical underpinnings of our own society. At its core, the franchise isn’t just an action-packed cyberpunk saga; it is a philosophical treatise exploring one of the cornerstones of democratic thought: the freedom of choice.

The Matrix as a Philosophical Inquiry
One of the fundamental questions posed by The Matrix is: What is free will without choice? The films challenge us to consider the very nature of freedom and whether it can truly exist without the ability to choose. Freedom is often lauded as a foundational ideal of human existence, but without the capacity to exercise choice, is one truly free? This is a question that has preoccupied philosophers for centuries, and The Matrix cleverly weaves it into its narrative framework.

In philosophy, freedom and choice are inherently linked. Choice is the mechanism through which freedom is exercised, allowing individuals to pursue their own paths, determine their destinies, and shape their personal identities. The more choice people have, the greater their sense of freedom and well-being. Conversely, when choice is removed or constrained, autonomy is diminished, and individuals become prisoners of forces beyond their control.

Neo’s Journey: The Three Forms of Freedom
The protagonist, Neo, embodies this philosophical inquiry. His evolution throughout the trilogy is a journey toward ultimate freedom, mirroring a deeper exploration of what it means to be truly independent. Each installment of the franchise represents a stage in this philosophical odyssey, corresponding to three distinct types of freedom:


1. Freedom From (The Matrix) – The first film introduces Neo as an individual trapped within the illusion of reality. This represents the initial stage of liberation: freedom from external constraints. In a broader sense, it is the struggle to break free from societal norms, imposed structures, and the deception of the world around us. Neo’s awakening from the Matrix signifies the first step toward true autonomy—gaining awareness of the illusion that binds him.






2. Freedom To (The Matrix Reloaded) – The second stage explores the freedom to act, to make choices, and to exert one’s will upon the world. Here, Neo learns that breaking free from an illusion is not enough; he must also navigate the complexities of decision-making. The film delves into the tension between choice and consequence, illustrating how free will is intertwined with responsibility.







3. Freedom To Be (The Matrix Revolutions) – The final stage of Neo’s journey is the realization of self-actualization—the freedom not only to act but to become who one is meant to be. This ultimate form of freedom transcends mere decision-making; it is the embodiment of one’s purpose. By the end of the trilogy, Neo fully embraces his identity as “The One,” illustrating the culmination of true autonomy and self-determination.





Neo’s counterpart in this philosophical struggle is Agent Smith, who represents the deterministic worldview. According to determinism, all actions and events are predetermined by external forces, making free will an illusion. Smith embodies this idea by asserting that choice is an illusion created by forces beyond our control. He serves as the ultimate antagonist not just in a physical sense, but as the ideological opponent to Neo’s belief in autonomy and self-determination.












Philosophical Character Analysis
The Matrix franchise is deeply philosophical, with each major character representing different perspectives on freedom, choice, and reality. Below is a deeper analysis of how various characters embody these themes:

1. Neo – The Embodiment of Free Will and Self-Actualization

Neo (Keanu Reeves), whose name is an anagram for “One,” represents the journey toward self-determination and enlightenment. At the start of the series, he is trapped within the illusion of the Matrix, unaware of his own potential. His journey reflects existentialist and libertarian ideas of free will—he gradually comes to understand that he is not bound by fate or external control, but rather, he has the power to shape his own destiny.




• Philosophical Connection: Neo’s journey is similar to Plato’s Allegory of the Cave, where he transitions from ignorance (inside the Matrix) to enlightenment (understanding reality).




![Plato (/ˈpleɪtoʊ/ PLAY-toe;[1] Greek: Πλάτων Plátōn; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher born in Athens during the Classical period. In Athens, Plato founded the Academy, a philosophical school where he taught the philosophical doctrines that would later become known as Platonism. Plato, or Platon, was a pen name derived, apparently, from the nickname given to him by his wrestling coach – allegedly a reference to his physical broadness. According to Alexander Polyhistor, quoted by Diogenes Laërtius, his actual name was Aristocles, son of Ariston, of the deme (suburb) Collytus, in Athens. Plato was an innovator of the written dialogue and dialectic forms in philosophy. He raised problems for what became all the major areas of both theoretical philosophy and practical philosophy. His most famous contribution is the theory of forms (or ideas), which has been interpreted as advancing a solution to what is now known as the problem of universals. He is the namesake of Platonic love and the Platonic solids. His own most decisive philosophical influences are usually thought to have been, along with Socrates, the pre-Socratics Pythagoras, Heraclitus, and Parmenides, although few of his predecessors' works remain extant and much of what is known about these figures today derives from Plato himself. Along with his teacher, Socrates, and student Aristotle, Plato is a central figure in the history of philosophy.[b] Unlike the work of nearly all of his contemporaries, Plato's entire body of work is believed to have survived intact for over 2,400 years. Although their popularity has fluctuated, Plato's works have consistently been read and studied. Through Neoplatonism Plato also greatly influenced both Christian (through e.g. Augustine of Hippo) and Islamic philosophy (through e.g. Al-Farabi). In modern times, Alfred North Whitehead famously said: "the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato." Photo Credit: Wikipedia Commons](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2023/09/Plato--683x1024.jpeg?ssl=1)
• Freedom Representation: He moves through the three stages of freedom (Freedom From, Freedom To, Freedom To Be), culminating in self-actualization.



2. Morpheus – The Philosopher-Guide (Socratic Influence)

Morpheus (Laurence Fishburne) plays the role of a mentor, much like Socrates, guiding Neo toward self-discovery. He does not impose beliefs but instead presents choices, allowing Neo to arrive at conclusions on his own (e.g., the red pill vs. blue pill decision).




• Philosophical Connection: Morpheus embodies epistemology—the study of knowledge—and is a stand-in for thinkers like Descartes, who doubted perceived reality (Cogito, ergo sum).


![René Descartes (/deɪˈkɑːrt/ day-KART, also UK: /ˈdeɪkɑːrt/ DAY-kart; French: [ʁəne dekaʁt] ⓘ; [note 3][11] 31 March 1596 – 11 February 1650)[12][13]: 58 was a French philosopher, scientist, and mathematician, widely considered a seminal figure in the emergence of modern philosophy and science. Mathematics was paramount to his method of inquiry, and he connected the previously separate fields of geometry and algebra into analytic geometry. Descartes spent much of his working life in the Dutch Republic, initially serving the Dutch States Army, and later becoming a central intellectual of the Dutch Golden Age.[14] Although he served a Protestant state and was later counted as a deist by critics, Descartes was Roman Catholic.[15][16] Many elements of Descartes's philosophy have precedents in late Aristotelianism, the revived Stoicism of the 16th century, or in earlier philosophers like Augustine. In his natural philosophy, he differed from the schools on two major points. First, he rejected the splitting of corporeal substance into matter and form; second, he rejected any appeal to final ends, divine or natural, in explaining natural phenomena.[17] In his theology, he insists on the absolute freedom of God's act of creation. Refusing to accept the authority of previous philosophers, Descartes frequently set his views apart from the philosophers who preceded him. In the opening section of the Passions of the Soul, an early modern treatise on emotions, Descartes goes so far as to assert that he will write on this topic "as if no one had written on these matters before." His best known philosophical statement is "cogito, ergo sum" ("I think, therefore I am"; French: Je pense, donc je suis), found in Discourse on the Method (1637, in French and Latin, 1644) and Principles of Philosophy (1644, in Latin, 1647 in French).[note 4] The statement has either been interpreted as a logical syllogism or as an intuitive thought.[18] Descartes has often been called the father of modern philosophy, and is largely seen as responsible for the increased attention given to epistemology in the 17th century.[19][note 5] He laid the foundation for 17th-century continental rationalism, later advocated by Spinoza and Leibniz, and was later opposed by the empiricist school of thought consisting of Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume. The rise of early modern rationalism—as a systematic school of philosophy in its own right for the first time in history—exerted an influence on modern Western thought in general, with the birth of two rationalistic philosophical systems of Descartes (Cartesianism) and Spinoza (Spinozism). It was the 17th-century arch-rationalists like Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz who have given the "Age of Reason" its name and place in history. Leibniz, Spinoza,[20] and Descartes were all well-versed in mathematics as well as philosophy, with Descartes and Leibniz additionally contributing to a variety of scientific disciplines.[21] Although only Leibniz is extensively recognized as a polymath, all three rationalists integrated disparate domains of knowledge into their respective works.[22] Descartes's Meditations on First Philosophy (1641) continues to be a standard text at most university philosophy departments. Descartes's influence in mathematics is equally apparent, being the namesake of the Cartesian coordinate system. He is credited as the father of analytic geometry—used in the discovery of infinitesimal calculus and analysis. Descartes was also one of the key figures in the Scientific Revolution.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/descartes.jpg?ssl=1)


• Freedom Representation: He believes that liberation begins with knowledge, emphasizing that one must first free their mind to achieve true autonomy.


3. Agent Smith – Determinism and Nihilism

Agent Smith (Hugo Weaving) is the ultimate counterpoint to Neo, representing deterministic and nihilistic philosophies. Unlike Neo, who believes in free will, Smith sees existence as meaningless and controlled by predetermined systems. His belief that humans are mere viruses and that everything follows a predefined path reflects a strictly fatalistic worldview.



• Philosophical Connection: Smith’s ideology aligns with hard determinism (Baruch Spinoza, B.F. Skinner), which suggests that free will is an illusion. His growing hatred for the Matrix itself also reflects a Nietzschean will to power—he wishes to destroy both the system and himself.


![Baruch (de) Spinoza[b] (24 November 1632 – 21 February 1677), known under his preferred Latinized pen name as Benedictus de Spinoza, was a philosopher of Portuguese-Jewish origin, who was born in the Dutch Republic. A forerunner of the Age of Enlightenment, Spinoza significantly influenced modern biblical criticism, 17th-century rationalism, and Dutch intellectual culture, establishing himself as one of the most important and radical philosophers of the early modern period.[15] Influenced by Stoicism, Thomas Hobbes, René Descartes,[16] Ibn Tufayl,[17] and heterodox Christians, Spinoza was a leading philosopher of the Dutch Golden Age.[18] Spinoza was born in Amsterdam to a Marrano family that fled Portugal for the more tolerant Dutch Republic. He received a traditional Jewish education, learning Hebrew and studying sacred texts within the Portuguese Jewish community, where his father was a prominent merchant. As a young man, Spinoza challenged rabbinic authority and questioned Jewish doctrines, leading to his permanent expulsion from his Jewish community in 1656. Following that expulsion, he distanced himself from all religious affiliations and devoted himself to philosophical inquiry and lens grinding. Spinoza attracted a dedicated circle of followers who gathered to discuss his writings and joined him in the intellectual pursuit of truth. Spinoza published little to avoid persecution and bans on his books. In his Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, described by Steven Nadler as "one of the most important books of Western thought", Spinoza questioned the divine origin of the Hebrew Bible and the nature of God while arguing that ecclesiastic authority should have no role in a secular, democratic state.[19][20] Ethics argues for a pantheistic view of God and explores the place of human freedom in a world devoid of theological, cosmological, and political moorings.[21] Rejecting messianism and the emphasis on the afterlife, Spinoza emphasized appreciating and valuing life for oneself and others. By advocating for individual liberty in its moral, psychological, and metaphysical dimensions, Spinoza helped establish the genre of political writing called secular theology.[22] Spinoza's philosophy spans nearly every area of philosophical discourse, including metaphysics, epistemology, political philosophy, ethics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of science. His friends posthumously published his works, captivating philosophers for the next two centuries. Celebrated as one of the most original and influential thinkers of the seventeenth century, Rebecca Goldstein dubbed him "the renegade Jew who gave us modernity.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/Baruch-Spinoza.jpeg?ssl=1)
![Baruch (de) Spinoza[b] (24 November 1632 – 21 February 1677), known under his preferred Latinized pen name as Benedictus de Spinoza, was a philosopher of Portuguese-Jewish origin, who was born in the Dutch Republic. A forerunner of the Age of Enlightenment, Spinoza significantly influenced modern biblical criticism, 17th-century rationalism, and Dutch intellectual culture, establishing himself as one of the most important and radical philosophers of the early modern period.[15] Influenced by Stoicism, Thomas Hobbes, René Descartes,[16] Ibn Tufayl,[17] and heterodox Christians, Spinoza was a leading philosopher of the Dutch Golden Age.[18] Spinoza was born in Amsterdam to a Marrano family that fled Portugal for the more tolerant Dutch Republic. He received a traditional Jewish education, learning Hebrew and studying sacred texts within the Portuguese Jewish community, where his father was a prominent merchant. As a young man, Spinoza challenged rabbinic authority and questioned Jewish doctrines, leading to his permanent expulsion from his Jewish community in 1656. Following that expulsion, he distanced himself from all religious affiliations and devoted himself to philosophical inquiry and lens grinding. Spinoza attracted a dedicated circle of followers who gathered to discuss his writings and joined him in the intellectual pursuit of truth. Spinoza published little to avoid persecution and bans on his books. In his Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, described by Steven Nadler as "one of the most important books of Western thought", Spinoza questioned the divine origin of the Hebrew Bible and the nature of God while arguing that ecclesiastic authority should have no role in a secular, democratic state.[19][20] Ethics argues for a pantheistic view of God and explores the place of human freedom in a world devoid of theological, cosmological, and political moorings.[21] Rejecting messianism and the emphasis on the afterlife, Spinoza emphasized appreciating and valuing life for oneself and others. By advocating for individual liberty in its moral, psychological, and metaphysical dimensions, Spinoza helped establish the genre of political writing called secular theology.[22] Spinoza's philosophy spans nearly every area of philosophical discourse, including metaphysics, epistemology, political philosophy, ethics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of science. His friends posthumously published his works, captivating philosophers for the next two centuries. Celebrated as one of the most original and influential thinkers of the seventeenth century, Rebecca Goldstein dubbed him "the renegade Jew who gave us modernity.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/Spinoza-1024x589.webp?ssl=1)
![Burrhus Frederic Skinner (March 20, 1904 – August 18, 1990) was an American psychologist, behaviorist, inventor, and social philosopher.[2][3][4][5] He was the Edgar Pierce Professor of Psychology at Harvard University from 1958 until his retirement in 1974.[6] Skinner developed behavior analysis, especially the philosophy of radical behaviorism,[7] and founded the experimental analysis of behavior, a school of experimental research psychology. He also used operant conditioning to strengthen behavior, considering the rate of response to be the most effective measure of response strength. To study operant conditioning, he invented the operant conditioning chamber (aka the Skinner box),[8] and to measure rate he invented the cumulative recorder. Using these tools, he and Charles Ferster produced Skinner's most influential experimental work, outlined in their 1957 book Schedules of Reinforcement.[9][10] Skinner was a prolific author, publishing 21 books and 180 articles.[11] He imagined the application of his ideas to the design of a human community in his 1948 utopian novel, Walden Two,[3] while his analysis of human behavior culminated in his 1958 work, Verbal Behavior.[12] Skinner, John B. Watson and Ivan Pavlov, are considered to be the pioneers of modern behaviorism. Accordingly, a June 2002 survey listed Skinner as the most influential psychologist of the 20th century](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/B.F.-Skinner.jpeg?ssl=1)
![Burrhus Frederic Skinner (March 20, 1904 – August 18, 1990) was an American psychologist, behaviorist, inventor, and social philosopher.[2][3][4][5] He was the Edgar Pierce Professor of Psychology at Harvard University from 1958 until his retirement in 1974.[6] Skinner developed behavior analysis, especially the philosophy of radical behaviorism,[7] and founded the experimental analysis of behavior, a school of experimental research psychology. He also used operant conditioning to strengthen behavior, considering the rate of response to be the most effective measure of response strength. To study operant conditioning, he invented the operant conditioning chamber (aka the Skinner box),[8] and to measure rate he invented the cumulative recorder. Using these tools, he and Charles Ferster produced Skinner's most influential experimental work, outlined in their 1957 book Schedules of Reinforcement.[9][10] Skinner was a prolific author, publishing 21 books and 180 articles.[11] He imagined the application of his ideas to the design of a human community in his 1948 utopian novel, Walden Two,[3] while his analysis of human behavior culminated in his 1958 work, Verbal Behavior.[12] Skinner, John B. Watson and Ivan Pavlov, are considered to be the pioneers of modern behaviorism. Accordingly, a June 2002 survey listed Skinner as the most influential psychologist of the 20th century](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/B.F.-Skinner-illusion-.png?ssl=1)
![Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche[ii] (15 October 1844 – 25 August 1900) was a German philosopher, philologist, poet, cultural critic, and composer who became one of the most influential of all modern thinkers.[14] He began his career as a classical philologist, turning to philosophy early in his academic career. In 1869, aged 24, Nietzsche became the youngest professor to hold the Chair of Classical Philology at the University of Basel. Plagued by health problems for most of his life, he resigned from the university in 1879, after which he completed much of his core writing in the following decade. In 1889, aged 44, he suffered a collapse and thereafter a complete loss of his mental faculties, with paralysis and vascular dementia. He lived his remaining years under the care of his family until his death in 1900. His works and his philosophy have fostered not only extensive scholarship, but also much popular interest and creative inspiration. Nietzsche's work spans philosophical polemics, poetry, cultural criticism, and fiction while displaying a fondness for aphorism and irony. Prominent elements of his philosophy include his radical critique of truth in favour of perspectivism; a genealogical critique of religion and Christian morality and a related theory of master–slave morality; the aesthetic affirmation of life in response to both the "death of God" and the profound crisis of nihilism; the notion of Apollonian and Dionysian forces; and a characterisation of the human subject as the expression of competing wills, collectively understood as the will to power. He also developed influential concepts such as the Übermensch and his doctrine of eternal return. In his later work, he became increasingly preoccupied with the creative powers of the individual to overcome cultural and moral mores in pursuit of new values and aesthetic health. His body of work touched a wide range of topics, including art, philology, history, music, religion, tragedy, culture, and science, and drew inspiration from Greek tragedy as well as figures such as Zoroaster, Arthur Schopenhauer, Ralph Waldo Emerson, Richard Wagner, Fyodor Dostoevsky, and Johann Wolfgang von Goethe. After Nietzsche’s death his sister, Elisabeth, became the curator and editor of his manuscripts. She edited his unpublished writings to fit her German ultranationalist ideology, often contradicting or obfuscating Nietzsche's stated opinions, which were explicitly opposed to antisemitism and nationalism. Through her published editions, Nietzsche's work became associated with fascism and Nazism. 20th-century scholars such as Walter Kaufmann, R. J. Hollingdale, and Georges Bataille defended Nietzsche against this interpretation, and corrected editions of his writings were soon made available. Nietzsche's thought enjoyed renewed popularity in the 1960s and his ideas have since had a profound impact on 20th- and early 21st-century thinkers across philosophy—especially in schools of continental philosophy such as existentialism, postmodernism, and post-structuralism—as well as art, literature, music, poetry, politics, and popular culture.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/Nietzsche-755x1024.jpg?ssl=1)
![Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche[ii] (15 October 1844 – 25 August 1900) was a German philosopher, philologist, poet, cultural critic, and composer who became one of the most influential of all modern thinkers.[14] He began his career as a classical philologist, turning to philosophy early in his academic career. In 1869, aged 24, Nietzsche became the youngest professor to hold the Chair of Classical Philology at the University of Basel. Plagued by health problems for most of his life, he resigned from the university in 1879, after which he completed much of his core writing in the following decade. In 1889, aged 44, he suffered a collapse and thereafter a complete loss of his mental faculties, with paralysis and vascular dementia. He lived his remaining years under the care of his family until his death in 1900. His works and his philosophy have fostered not only extensive scholarship, but also much popular interest and creative inspiration. Nietzsche's work spans philosophical polemics, poetry, cultural criticism, and fiction while displaying a fondness for aphorism and irony. Prominent elements of his philosophy include his radical critique of truth in favour of perspectivism; a genealogical critique of religion and Christian morality and a related theory of master–slave morality; the aesthetic affirmation of life in response to both the "death of God" and the profound crisis of nihilism; the notion of Apollonian and Dionysian forces; and a characterisation of the human subject as the expression of competing wills, collectively understood as the will to power. He also developed influential concepts such as the Übermensch and his doctrine of eternal return. In his later work, he became increasingly preoccupied with the creative powers of the individual to overcome cultural and moral mores in pursuit of new values and aesthetic health. His body of work touched a wide range of topics, including art, philology, history, music, religion, tragedy, culture, and science, and drew inspiration from Greek tragedy as well as figures such as Zoroaster, Arthur Schopenhauer, Ralph Waldo Emerson, Richard Wagner, Fyodor Dostoevsky, and Johann Wolfgang von Goethe. After Nietzsche’s death his sister, Elisabeth, became the curator and editor of his manuscripts. She edited his unpublished writings to fit her German ultranationalist ideology, often contradicting or obfuscating Nietzsche's stated opinions, which were explicitly opposed to antisemitism and nationalism. Through her published editions, Nietzsche's work became associated with fascism and Nazism. 20th-century scholars such as Walter Kaufmann, R. J. Hollingdale, and Georges Bataille defended Nietzsche against this interpretation, and corrected editions of his writings were soon made available. Nietzsche's thought enjoyed renewed popularity in the 1960s and his ideas have since had a profound impact on 20th- and early 21st-century thinkers across philosophy—especially in schools of continental philosophy such as existentialism, postmodernism, and post-structuralism—as well as art, literature, music, poetry, politics, and popular culture.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/Nietzschean-will-to-power-2.jpg?ssl=1)
![Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche[ii] (15 October 1844 – 25 August 1900) was a German philosopher, philologist, poet, cultural critic, and composer who became one of the most influential of all modern thinkers.[14] He began his career as a classical philologist, turning to philosophy early in his academic career. In 1869, aged 24, Nietzsche became the youngest professor to hold the Chair of Classical Philology at the University of Basel. Plagued by health problems for most of his life, he resigned from the university in 1879, after which he completed much of his core writing in the following decade. In 1889, aged 44, he suffered a collapse and thereafter a complete loss of his mental faculties, with paralysis and vascular dementia. He lived his remaining years under the care of his family until his death in 1900. His works and his philosophy have fostered not only extensive scholarship, but also much popular interest and creative inspiration. Nietzsche's work spans philosophical polemics, poetry, cultural criticism, and fiction while displaying a fondness for aphorism and irony. Prominent elements of his philosophy include his radical critique of truth in favour of perspectivism; a genealogical critique of religion and Christian morality and a related theory of master–slave morality; the aesthetic affirmation of life in response to both the "death of God" and the profound crisis of nihilism; the notion of Apollonian and Dionysian forces; and a characterisation of the human subject as the expression of competing wills, collectively understood as the will to power. He also developed influential concepts such as the Übermensch and his doctrine of eternal return. In his later work, he became increasingly preoccupied with the creative powers of the individual to overcome cultural and moral mores in pursuit of new values and aesthetic health. His body of work touched a wide range of topics, including art, philology, history, music, religion, tragedy, culture, and science, and drew inspiration from Greek tragedy as well as figures such as Zoroaster, Arthur Schopenhauer, Ralph Waldo Emerson, Richard Wagner, Fyodor Dostoevsky, and Johann Wolfgang von Goethe. After Nietzsche’s death his sister, Elisabeth, became the curator and editor of his manuscripts. She edited his unpublished writings to fit her German ultranationalist ideology, often contradicting or obfuscating Nietzsche's stated opinions, which were explicitly opposed to antisemitism and nationalism. Through her published editions, Nietzsche's work became associated with fascism and Nazism. 20th-century scholars such as Walter Kaufmann, R. J. Hollingdale, and Georges Bataille defended Nietzsche against this interpretation, and corrected editions of his writings were soon made available. Nietzsche's thought enjoyed renewed popularity in the 1960s and his ideas have since had a profound impact on 20th- and early 21st-century thinkers across philosophy—especially in schools of continental philosophy such as existentialism, postmodernism, and post-structuralism—as well as art, literature, music, poetry, politics, and popular culture.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/Nietzschean-will-to-power.jpg?ssl=1)
• Freedom Representation: He is a representation of the system’s control and the philosophical debate of whether anyone truly has choice.


4. The Oracle – The Paradox of Choice and Soft Determinism

The Oracle (Gloria Foster/Mary Alice), despite being a program within the Matrix, is one of the most enigmatic characters when it comes to free will. She provides cryptic guidance, subtly nudging people toward certain decisions while maintaining that they still have choices.



• Philosophical Connection: The Oracle embodies compatibilism—the belief that free will and determinism can coexist. Thinkers like David Hume and Immanuel Kant argued that while some events may be determined, individuals still exercise meaningful choices within those constraints.







• Freedom Representation: She acknowledges that choice exists, but often leads individuals toward their destined path, reinforcing the paradox of freedom within a seemingly predetermined system.


5. The Merovingian – Determinism and the Illusion of Choice

The Merovingian (Lambert Wilson), a rogue program who deals in cause and effect, takes a cynical view on choice, arguing that free will is an illusion. He believes that every action is merely the result of a preceding cause—what he calls causality.



• Philosophical Connection: His ideology is rooted in determinism and logical positivism. He reflects thinkers like Pierre-Simon Laplace, who argued that if one knew all the variables of the universe, they could predict all future events.





• Freedom Representation: He directly opposes the idea of free will, claiming that all actions are dictated by necessity, not genuine choice.


6. Trinity – The Emotional and Personal Aspect of Freedom

Trinity (Carrie-Anne Moss), whose name suggests unity and completeness, represents the personal dimension of freedom. While Neo’s journey is philosophical and Morpheus’s is epistemological, Trinity provides the emotional core of autonomy. She embodies the ability to love and choose freely despite external constraints.



• Philosophical Connection: She resonates with existentialist thinkers like Simone de Beauvoir and Jean-Paul Sartre, who emphasized personal agency in relationships and self-definition.





![Few philosophers have been as famous in their own life-time as Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–80). Many thousands of Parisians packed into his public lecture, Existentialism is a Humanism, towards the end of 1945 and the culmination of World War 2. That lecture offered an accessible version of his difficult treatise, Being and Nothingness (1943), which had been published two years earlier, and it also responded to contemporary Marxist and Christian critics of Sartre’s “existentialism”. Sartre was much more than just a traditional academic philosopher, however, and this begins to explain his renown. He also wrote highly influential works of literature, inflected by philosophical concerns, like Nausea (1938), The Roads to Freedom trilogy (1945–49), and plays like No Exit (1947), Flies (1947), and Dirty Hands (1948), to name just a few. He founded and co-edited Les Temps Modernes and mobilised various forms of political protest and action. In short, he was a celebrity and public intellectual par excellence, especially in the period after Liberation through to the early 1960s. Responding to some calls to prosecute Sartre for civil disobedience, the then French President Charles de Gaulle replied that you don’t arrest Voltaire. While Sartre’s public renown remains, his work has had less academic attention in the last thirty or so years ago, and earlier in France, dating roughly from the rise of “post-structuralism” in the 1960s. Although Gilles Deleuze dedicated an article to his “master” in 1964 in the wake of Sartre’s attempt to refuse the Nobel Prize for literature (Deleuze 2004), Michel Foucault influentially declared Sartre’s late work was a “magnificent and pathetic attempt of a man of the nineteenth century to think the twentieth century” (Foucault 1966 [1994: 541–2])[1]. In this entry, however, we seek to show what remains alive and of ongoing philosophical interest in Sartre, covering many of the most important insights of his most famous philosophical book, Being and Nothingness. In addition, significant parts of his oeuvre remain under-appreciated and thus we seek to introduce them. Little attention has been given to Sartre’s earlier, psychologically motivated philosophical works, such as Imagination (1936) or its sequel, The Imaginary (1940). Likewise, few philosophers have seriously grappled with Sartre’s later works, including his massive two-volume Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960), or his various works in existential psychoanalysis that examine the works of Genet and Baudelaire, as well as his multi-volume masterpiece on Flaubert, The Family Idiot (1971–2). These are amongst the works of which Sartre was most proud and we outline some of their core ideas and claims.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/Jean-Paul-Sartre-788x1024.webp?ssl=1)
![Few philosophers have been as famous in their own life-time as Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–80). Many thousands of Parisians packed into his public lecture, Existentialism is a Humanism, towards the end of 1945 and the culmination of World War 2. That lecture offered an accessible version of his difficult treatise, Being and Nothingness (1943), which had been published two years earlier, and it also responded to contemporary Marxist and Christian critics of Sartre’s “existentialism”. Sartre was much more than just a traditional academic philosopher, however, and this begins to explain his renown. He also wrote highly influential works of literature, inflected by philosophical concerns, like Nausea (1938), The Roads to Freedom trilogy (1945–49), and plays like No Exit (1947), Flies (1947), and Dirty Hands (1948), to name just a few. He founded and co-edited Les Temps Modernes and mobilised various forms of political protest and action. In short, he was a celebrity and public intellectual par excellence, especially in the period after Liberation through to the early 1960s. Responding to some calls to prosecute Sartre for civil disobedience, the then French President Charles de Gaulle replied that you don’t arrest Voltaire. While Sartre’s public renown remains, his work has had less academic attention in the last thirty or so years ago, and earlier in France, dating roughly from the rise of “post-structuralism” in the 1960s. Although Gilles Deleuze dedicated an article to his “master” in 1964 in the wake of Sartre’s attempt to refuse the Nobel Prize for literature (Deleuze 2004), Michel Foucault influentially declared Sartre’s late work was a “magnificent and pathetic attempt of a man of the nineteenth century to think the twentieth century” (Foucault 1966 [1994: 541–2])[1]. In this entry, however, we seek to show what remains alive and of ongoing philosophical interest in Sartre, covering many of the most important insights of his most famous philosophical book, Being and Nothingness. In addition, significant parts of his oeuvre remain under-appreciated and thus we seek to introduce them. Little attention has been given to Sartre’s earlier, psychologically motivated philosophical works, such as Imagination (1936) or its sequel, The Imaginary (1940). Likewise, few philosophers have seriously grappled with Sartre’s later works, including his massive two-volume Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960), or his various works in existential psychoanalysis that examine the works of Genet and Baudelaire, as well as his multi-volume masterpiece on Flaubert, The Family Idiot (1971–2). These are amongst the works of which Sartre was most proud and we outline some of their core ideas and claims.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/41-4-FA-Sartre.jpg?ssl=1)
![Few philosophers have been as famous in their own life-time as Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–80). Many thousands of Parisians packed into his public lecture, Existentialism is a Humanism, towards the end of 1945 and the culmination of World War 2. That lecture offered an accessible version of his difficult treatise, Being and Nothingness (1943), which had been published two years earlier, and it also responded to contemporary Marxist and Christian critics of Sartre’s “existentialism”. Sartre was much more than just a traditional academic philosopher, however, and this begins to explain his renown. He also wrote highly influential works of literature, inflected by philosophical concerns, like Nausea (1938), The Roads to Freedom trilogy (1945–49), and plays like No Exit (1947), Flies (1947), and Dirty Hands (1948), to name just a few. He founded and co-edited Les Temps Modernes and mobilised various forms of political protest and action. In short, he was a celebrity and public intellectual par excellence, especially in the period after Liberation through to the early 1960s. Responding to some calls to prosecute Sartre for civil disobedience, the then French President Charles de Gaulle replied that you don’t arrest Voltaire. While Sartre’s public renown remains, his work has had less academic attention in the last thirty or so years ago, and earlier in France, dating roughly from the rise of “post-structuralism” in the 1960s. Although Gilles Deleuze dedicated an article to his “master” in 1964 in the wake of Sartre’s attempt to refuse the Nobel Prize for literature (Deleuze 2004), Michel Foucault influentially declared Sartre’s late work was a “magnificent and pathetic attempt of a man of the nineteenth century to think the twentieth century” (Foucault 1966 [1994: 541–2])[1]. In this entry, however, we seek to show what remains alive and of ongoing philosophical interest in Sartre, covering many of the most important insights of his most famous philosophical book, Being and Nothingness. In addition, significant parts of his oeuvre remain under-appreciated and thus we seek to introduce them. Little attention has been given to Sartre’s earlier, psychologically motivated philosophical works, such as Imagination (1936) or its sequel, The Imaginary (1940). Likewise, few philosophers have seriously grappled with Sartre’s later works, including his massive two-volume Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960), or his various works in existential psychoanalysis that examine the works of Genet and Baudelaire, as well as his multi-volume masterpiece on Flaubert, The Family Idiot (1971–2). These are amongst the works of which Sartre was most proud and we outline some of their core ideas and claims.](https://i0.wp.com/moviestohistory.com/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/Existentialism-is-nothing-else-but-an-attempt-to-draw-the-full-conclusions-from-a-consistently-atheistic-position-Jean-Paul-Sartre-1905-1980-1024x576.jpg?ssl=1)
• Freedom Representation: She showcases that true freedom isn’t just about breaking from control, but also about embracing one’s identity and passions.


7. The Architect – The Systematic Control of Choice

The Architect (Helmut Bakaitis), the creator of the Matrix, represents the illusion of structured choice. He allows humans to believe they have free will but actually controls their decisions through predictive algorithms.



• Philosophical Connection: He aligns with panopticism (Michel Foucault), where power is maintained by giving people an illusion of control. He also represents Kantian transcendental idealism, where reality is shaped by predefined structures that humans cannot fully comprehend.







• Freedom Representation: He is the ultimate embodiment of systemic oppression, proving that even within supposed autonomy, people are still manipulated by larger forces.


The Matrix Resurrections: A New Layer of Inquiry

In 2021, The Matrix Resurrections, directed by Lana Wachowski, was released, recontextualizing the themes of the original trilogy while introducing new philosophical questions about choice, memory, and identity. While the previous films explored the process of awakening and self-determination, Resurrections delves into the idea of control through nostalgia, rewriting personal history, and the commodification of choice.




Neo, now living under the identity of Thomas Anderson, is once again trapped inside the Matrix, but this time, he is manipulated into believing that his past experiences were merely the plot of a successful video game he created. His past has been reframed as fiction, stripping him of the certainty he once had about reality and choice. This raises a new question: If our perception of the past is manipulated, can we still exercise true freedom? If memory itself is unreliable, does choice still hold meaning?




The film also introduces a reimagined Morpheus (Yahya Abdul-Mateen II), no longer the same mentor figure but instead a program that merges elements of the original Morpheus and Agent Smith. This fusion challenges the traditional duality of free will vs. determinism, suggesting that identities and ideologies are more fluid than previously believed. Likewise, a new version of Agent Smith (Jonathan Groff) emerges, played by a different actor and with a revised purpose—rather than being the embodiment of pure determinism, he becomes a self-aware agent seeking his own kind of liberation, adding complexity to his original role.


Trinity’s arc is perhaps the most radical departure from the original trilogy. Whereas before, she was an active force in Neo’s journey to self-discovery, she now exists within the Matrix as Tiffany, a woman who does not remember her past and is trapped within the constructs of a false life. Her journey to reclaiming her identity underscores a new philosophical angle: What happens when choice is taken from us not by external oppression, but by the reconfiguration of our own perception of reality? In Resurrections, the act of reclaiming memory becomes an act of rebellion, reinforcing the idea that freedom is not just about making choices—it is about remembering that we have the power to choose at all.





The antagonist of Resurrections, The Analyst (Neil Patrick Harris), represents a new form of control distinct from the Architect’s systematic oppression. The Analyst maintains order by leveraging human emotions, particularly fear and desire, to keep people complacent. He argues that people do not actually want true freedom; rather, they prefer the illusion of choice within comfortable constraints. This represents a shift from the previous films’ focus on determinism vs. free will to a more postmodern critique of manipulation and self-delusion.


The Matrix as a Reflection of Freedom’s Complexity

The Matrix franchise presents a multi-layered exploration of freedom, choice, and control. Each character serves as a philosophical touchstone, illustrating various perspectives on autonomy:
• Neo represents self-determination and free will.

• Morpheus embodies the pursuit of knowledge as the first step to liberation.

• Agent Smith argues for deterministic fatalism.

• The Oracle plays with the paradox of choice.

• The Merovingian promotes a cynical deterministic worldview.

• Trinity represents the emotional, existential aspect of autonomy.

• The Architect reveals the hidden structures that control freedom.

Together, these perspectives weave a complex narrative that forces audiences to ask, What does it truly mean to be free? Just as Neo’s journey is about breaking free from illusions, so too is the film’s challenge to its viewers—to question their reality, examine their choices, and seek their own version of “The One.”


The Matrix as a New Lens on Freedom
This is why The Matrix remains one of my favorite film franchises. It presents a stunning blend of philosophy and storytelling, weaving complex existential questions into an engaging narrative. By stripping away the action sequences, CGI, and dystopian aesthetics, we are left with a profound meditation on what it means to be free. The films invite us to examine our own lives and consider the choices we make—are we truly exercising free will, or are we merely following a predetermined script?





Perhaps, with this perspective, The Matrix can be seen in an entirely new light. Rather than a convoluted sci-fi epic, it becomes a lens through which we can examine our own beliefs about autonomy, choice, and the essence of human freedom. And in doing so, it challenges us to ask the same question that has echoed throughout history: Are we truly free?


One Reply to “Freedom, Choice, and The Matrix: A Philosophical Journey…”